SciELO - Scientific Electronic Library Online

 
vol.15 número2What should the board of management of a pension fund consider when dealing with death claims involving surviving cohabitants? índice de autoresíndice de materiabúsqueda de artículos
Home Pagelista alfabética de revistas  

Servicios Personalizados

Articulo

Indicadores

Links relacionados

  • En proceso de indezaciónCitado por Google
  • En proceso de indezaciónSimilares en Google

Compartir


Potchefstroom Electronic Law Journal (PELJ)

versión On-line ISSN 1727-3781

PER vol.15 no.2 Potchefstroom ago. 2012

 

ARTICLES

 

But is it speech? making critical sense of the dominant constitutional discourse on pornography, morality and harm under the pervasive influence of united states first amendment jurisprudence

 

 

L van der Poll

BA, LLB, LLM LLD (Stell), Associate Professor, Department of Public Law and Jurisprudence, Faculty of Law, University of the Western Cape. E-mail: lvdpoll@uwc.ac.za

 

 


SUMMARY

Under the pervasive influence of United States First Amendment jurisprudence, adult gender-specific sexually explicit (or "pornographic") material is conceptualized, and thus protected in the "marketplace of ideas", as a particular mode of expression; to be viewed as part of the fabric of an open, free and democratic society. The values which free expression are seen to promote centre upon the advancement of political debate and promotion of personal self-fulfilment and autonomy.
Attempts to conceptualise sexually explicit material within a gender-specific human rights framework present distinct challenges which, in a patriarchal legal and political design, appear to be near insurmountable. These challenges seem to be related to the enduring impact of the common law conception of obscenity (with its strong moralistic overtones) on the jurisprudence of the United States Supreme Court, coupled with a subjective libertarian-inspired test, and the Supreme Court's general reluctance (also echoed by the South African Constitutional Court) to consider a gender-specific conception of harm emanating from feminist arguments premised upon women's constitutional interests in human dignity, equality and bodily integrity.
The social revolution of the 1960s, coupled with the women's liberation movement, called for a distinct departure from the traditional conception of sexually explicit material as a mode of constitutionally defendable free speech and expression, a conception which unavoidably calls for a moralistic approach, separating acceptable forms of expression from those not deemed worthy of (constitutional) protection (termed "obscenity", specifically created to satisfy the "prurient interest").
The Supreme Court's obscenity jurisprudence is characterised by two key features. First, the court subscribes to an abstract concept of free speech, which proceeds from the assumption that all speech is of equal value, and thereby surmises that "non-obscene" sexually explicit material has social value, as do esteemed works of literature and art. Secondly, the court assumes that all individuals have equal access to the means of expression and dissemination of ideas and thus fails to acknowledge substantive (and gendered) structural inequalities.
A closer inspection reveals that the Supreme Court's justification of why freedom of expression is such a fundamental freedom in a constitutional democracy (and the reason that "non-obscene" sexually explicit material consequently enjoys constitutional protection) is highly suspect, both intellectually and philosophically. And yet the South African Constitutional Court has explicitly recognised the same philosophical justification as the basis for free speech and expression. The Constitutional Court has, in fact, both supported and emphasised the idea that freedom of expression stands central to the concepts of democracy and political transformation through participation, and has expressly confirmed the association between freedom of expression and the political rights safeguarded under the Bill of Rights. Moreover, the Constitutional Court has also endorsed the conception of adult gender-specific sexually explicit material as a form of free expression.
And yet by embracing a moralistic, libertarian model of free expression, the very ideal of a free, democratic and equal society, one in which women can live secure from the threat of harm, is put at risk. A moralistic, libertarian model is simply not capable of conceptualising sexually explicit material as a possible violation of women's fundamental interests in equality, dignity and physical integrity.
This article has a two-fold objective. The first is to critically examine the dominant discourse on adult gender-specific sexually explicit material emanating from United States jurisprudence (and its resonance in South African constitutional thought), and secondly, to assess whether this particular conception is sensitive to the possible constitutional harm which may result from an abstract liberal-inspired accommodation of sexually explicit material in an imagined free and open democratic society, such as the one presented by the South African legal and constitutional contexts.

Keywords: Sexually explicit material · obscenity · morality · harm · free speech and expression · First Amendment · female sexuality · human rights framework · constitutional jurisprudence


 

 

L van der Poll

I shall not today attempt to define the kinds of material I understand to be [hard core pornography]; and perhaps I could never succeed in intelligibly doing so. But I know it when I see it.

Mr Justice Potter Stewart might have known obscenity when he saw it, but with respect, I do not, nor would in any way claim to any intuitive and immediate recognition of what is indecent.1

Obscenity law is concerned with morality, meaning good and evil, virtue and vice. The concerns of feminism with power and powerlessness are first political, not moral. From the feminist perspective, obscenity is a moral idea; pornography is a political practice. Obscenity is abstract; pornography is concrete. Obscenity conveys moral condemnation as a predicate to legal condemnation. Pornography identifies a political practice that is predicated on power and powerlessness - a practice that is, in fact, legally protected. The two concepts represent two entirely different things.2

 

1 Introduction

The quest for a suitable theoretical mould within which to explore the possible constitutional consequences of adult3gender-specific4sexually explicit material5(often referred to as "obscene" or even "pornographic" material) is, by its very nature, premised on a particular conception (or definition) of such material. Although various attempts to produce a legal definition of sexually explicit material have been criticised as either too vague or too broad (or even "under broad"),6some attempt at a definition remains an essential preliminary to any meaningful discussion thereof. The theoretical mould(s) within which a definition is (are) cast will largely determine the extent of an effective constitutional challenge to material deemed sexually explicit and, in turn, set guidelines for its possible regulation or prohibition.

The constitutional parameters within which these debates should arguably be situated are determined by various factors. These, amongst other, include the political and constitutional history of a country, its current constitutional dispensation, its fundamental constitutional values and the founding principles of its democratic order.7In the event of a constitutional democracy (which is characterised by the presence of a supreme constitution with a justiciable bill of rights) a legal definition of gender-specific sexually explicit material formulated with the objective to frame it as a possible infringement of women's fundamental rights and freedoms must be mindful of these parameters. Certain constitutional rights and/or values might have to be prioritised and this process may be guided and/or influenced by various factors, each of which requires careful consideration.

And yet attempts to conceptualise sexually explicit material within a gender-specific human rights framework present distinct challenges which, in a patriarchal legal and political design, would appear to be near insurmountable. These challenges would seem to be related to the enduring impact of the common law conception of obscenity (with its strong moralistic overtones) on the jurisprudence of the Supreme Court of the United States, coupled with a subjective libertarian-inspired test,8and the Supreme Court's general reluctance (echoed also by the South African Constitutional Court)9to consider a gender-specific conception of harm emanating from feminist arguments premised upon women's constitutional interests in human dignity, equality and bodily integrity.

It is important to note that this article neither concerns so-called "child"10or "gay" and "lesbian"11sexually explicit material, nor does it proceed from the popular philosophical vantage point that sexually explicit material causes harm to, or threatens, the general moral character of society.

The article thus has essentially a two-fold objective. The first is to critically examine the dominant discourse on adult gender-specific sexually explicit material resulting from the pervasive influence of United States Supreme Court jurisprudence (which has found clear resonance in South African constitutional thought), and secondly, to assess whether this particular conception is indeed sensitive to the possible constitutional harm which may result from an abstract liberal-inspired accommodation of sexually explicit material in an imagined free and open democratic society, such as the one presented by the South African legal and constitutional contexts.

With these objectives in mind, the common law conception of sexually explicit material, with particular reference to its impression on the constitutional jurisprudence of the United States, will first be examined briefly.

 

2 Obscenity under Common Law

One of the oldest definitions of sexually explicit material under common law is found in the Obscene Publications Act of 1857,12revisited in 1868 by the Queen's Bench in Regina v Hicklin.13The standard established by the Queen's Bench is a telling example of the strong moralistic nuances of Victorian legal thinking, both in its articulation of a positive obligation on the state to protect citizens who are particularly susceptible to immoral influences and in its attempt to ascertain the effect of obscene material on corruptible and susceptible minds.14Consequently, any bona fideintention on the part of a distributor and/or publisher of obscene material was irrelevant under English common law.

It is somewhat perplexing that the common law approach to obscenity remained largely unchallenged in the United States for eighty nine years.15Since the enquiry at common law was not conducted against the backdrop of a constitutional democracy, its usefulness remained limited at best. Two leading decisions by the Supreme Court, set sixteen years apart, have sought to establish a golden mean between the First Amendment16guarantees of freedom of speech and the press and the recognised right of federal states to proscribe specific categories of sexually explicit material. These two judgments will be critically examined below.

 

3 Obscenity and the First Amendment: The Roth and Miller Judgments

In both Roth v United States17and Miller v California18the Supreme Court confirmed that the question whether sexually explicit material would enjoy any protection had to be considered under the First Amendment to the United States Constitution.

In tracing the history of the First Amendment in Roth, Brennan J found obscenity to be "utterlywithout redeeming social importance",19a rejection mirrored in the "universal belief" which was on occasion articulated by the Supreme Court as follows:

[t]here are certain well-defined and narrow limited classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of which have never been thought to raise any Constitutional problem. These include the lewd and obscene . . . It has been well observed that such utterances are no essential part of any exposition of ideas, and are of such slight social value as a step to truth that any benefit which may be derived from them is clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and morality.20

And yet although the Supreme Court found that the common law standard had to be rejected as an inevitable encroachment upon the constitutional guarantees entrenched by the First Amendment,21the terminology favoured by Brennan J nevertheless points to a distinctly puritanical (and thus moralistic) condemnation of material deemed obscene. Obscene material accordingly "deals with sex in a manner appealing to the prurient interest", and thus constitute "material having a tendency to excite lustful thoughts".22

Yet subsequent to Roth, no majority of the Supreme Court could agree on a standard to subject obscene material to regulation. The period 1957 to 1973 saw "a variety of views among the members of the Court unmatched in any other course of constitutional adjudication".23One matter that was, however, categorically settled was that obscene material, defined in terms of appealing to the "prurient interest", "patently offensive" and "utterly without redeeming social value",24enjoyed no protection under the First Amendment.

Then in 1973, the Supreme Court was called upon to review a group of obscenity cases, involving what Harlan J on occasion exasperatedly referred to as the "intractable obscenity problem".25Miller v California,26one of the aforementioned cases under review, constitutes an interesting variation on the Supreme Court's obscenity jurisprudence of the preceding twenty one years27in that it, for example, constitutes the first judicial acknowledgment of the term "pornography".28

According to Burger CJ, the appropriate standard for obscenity should forthwith only target "patently offensive hard core sexual conduct"29or "hard core pornography",30and thus material no longer needs to be "utterly without redeeming social value" to fall foul of the First Amendment.31And since obscenity is to be determined by applying contemporary community standards (instead of "unascertainable" national standards),32federal legislatures can justifiably proscribe obscenity if the danger exists of offending the "sensibilities" of unwilling (adult) recipients of "sexually oriented material" or of exposure thereof to minors.33Evidently unaware of the extensive body of feminist literature on the meaning and gender politics of "pornography", Burger CJ concluded that "obscene material" thus has a specific legal meaning, namely "obscene material which deals with sex".34

But even though Burger CJ essentially reaffirmed the Supreme Court's position, he endeavoured to formulate more "concrete standards" than those produced by the "somewhat tortured history of the court's obscenity decisions".35To realize this objective, he set forth to formulate the new standard of obscenity as follows:

[t]he basic guidelines for the trier of fact must be: (a) whether 'the average person, applying contemporary community standards'36would find that the work, taken as a whole, appeals to the prurient interest; (b) whether the work depicts or describes, in a patently offensive way, sexual conduct specifically defined by the applicable state law; and (c) whether the work, taken as a whole, lacks serious literary, artistic, political or scientific value. We do not adopt as a constitutional standard the 'utterly without redeeming social value' test of Memoirs v Massachusetts.37

Prurience and offensiveness, essentially, will be questions of fact. Consequently, works which, taken as a whole, have serious literary, artistic, political or scientific value will enjoy protection under the First Amendment, unlike the "public portrayal of hard core sexual conduct for its own sake".38

 

4 Opening Pandora's Box: The Supreme Court's Conception of "Pornography"

The Supreme Court's conception and treatment of obscenity or, to use its own terminology, "hard core pornography"39is problematic for a number of reasons. Apart from the court's insistence on engaging an abstract libertarian paradigm for assessing the possible constitutional implications of sexually explicit material (in which common law-inspired moralistic sentiments continue to prevail), two additional aspects of the court's jurisprudence raise particular difficulties. The first relates to the court's justification for examining the matter under the First Amendment, and in what follows below, particular attention will be given to the court's intellectual and philosophical justification for freedom of expression and its constitutional consequences. The second problematic aspect relates to the shortcomings of a libertarian conception of harm, coupled with the constitutional standard proposed in Miller.

The validity of many of the assumptions that underpin the court's obscenity jurisprudence appears not merely insensitive, but indeed oblivious, to the dynamics of male privilege and control in relation to the actual social realities of women in a legal and political society founded on libertarian principles. The court therefore struggles to see that the very reason why sexually explicit material could be construed as a problem within a discourse on women's fundamental rights and freedoms may in some way be related to the tenets of individuality, autonomy and neutrality which indeed sustain its conception of obscenity. Consequently, the validity of the court's assumptions about the nature of debate (and ideas), the function of the state and the degree of autonomy and power enjoyed by individuals in the liberal state all warrant serious reconsideration. 

4.1 The philosophy of obscenity

The Supreme Court's obscenity jurisprudence is characterised by two key features. First, the court subscribes to an abstract concept of free speech, which proceeds from the assumption that all speech is of equal value, and thereby surmises that non-obscene sexually explicit material has social value, as do esteemed works of literature and art. Secondly, the court assumes that all individuals have equal access to the means of expression and dissemination of ideas and thus fails to acknowledge substantive structural inequalities.

The court ought to be aware that systemic inequalities make it difficult for some individuals to express their views, if not in practice then at least in theory. Consequently, the much favoured liberal argument that more speech should be allowed as a means to rectify such imbalances could thus, in reality, serve to exacerbate a deeply entrenched system of inequality. It is an utter fallacy to presume that freedom of expression is possessed by men and women, or even different racial or ethnic groups,40in equal measure. Due to systemic gender and sex inequality, women find it difficult to enjoy the full benefits of free speech.

The structural power imbalance between men and women is a crucial determinant of the degree to which the latter have access to the means of expression. For one, women lack the resources required to articulate their unique experiences with the result that they could be effectively excluded from public discourse. The marketplace of ideas paradigm is both philosophically and in practice linked to the idea of capitalism. In reality, it serves to accommodate those with the most power and ultimately gives them access to the widest dissemination of their ideas. Women are furthermore silenced through endemic sexual abuse and violence which render it difficult to articulate their own experiences in a creditable way. The manner in which criminal law treated a female complainant in a rape or sexual harassment case underscores this point.41The Supreme Court does not seem mindful of the fact that an abstract system of free speech lacks the substantive means to empower those who have systematically been excluded from public discourse on the basis of race, gender and/or sex.42An abstract system of free speech cannot, therefore, be the legal priority for any system characterised by institutionalised racial and gender oppression. I agree with Andrea Dworkin who argues that:

[i]f equality interests can never matter against first amendment challenges, then speech becomes a weapon used by the haves against the have-nots; and the First Amendment, not balances against equality rights of the have-nots, becomes an intolerable instrument of dispossession, not a safeguard of human liberty.43

An investigation launched by the South African Human Rights Commission (the Commission) into racism in the South African media further underscores this point.44Submissions before a hearing of the Commission by black editors and journalists highlighted racial stereotyping, marginalisation and prejudice in the (then) still predominantly white owned South African media. Submissions by the latter largely denied that these problems continue(d) to exist.45

It need not be argued that free speech, to the degree that it occurred in apartheid South Africa, was largely conceived to secure a particular political end, namely to entrench institutionalised racism and sexism as a means to secure patriarchal minority rule.46Since speech was intended to entrench the political status quo, those groups in South African society who did not enjoy fundamental freedoms prior to the adoption of the Interim Constitution in 1994,47appear not to have been secured these freedoms to the fullest extent in practice in post-apartheid South Africa either. It therefore makes no sense to assume that (previously) marginalised groups will enjoy the same measure of free speech through an abstract system, for an abstract system does not provide a substantive guarantee of free speech for those who were (and may continue to be) socially and politically disempowered. In a hierarchal society the speech of the (socially and politically) powerful group will inevitably dominate public discourse48and thus distort the "free" competition in the marketplace of ideas which effectively serves to maintain structural racial and sex inequality. The animated (and at times antagonistic) discourse evoked by the Protection of Information Bill49which proposes to allow officials in virtually all organs of state to classify information, the publication or possession of which will be subject to criminal liability, together with the establishment of a Media Appeals Tribunal,50reinforces the argument that the control of access to information (and control of the media generally) serve a distinct political objective, one which is intended to ensconce socio-political power and control.51

The two aspects of the Supreme Court's obscenity jurisprudence which raise particular difficulties are, of course, interrelated. The court's standard of obscenity (i.e. its test in three parts)52is, for example, the result of a particular philosophical framework, coupled with a particular interpretation of the (modern) doctrine of free speech. The fact that the Miller test has been widely criticised, especially for lack of clarity and effectiveness, means that American society is flooded with "non-obscene" sexually explicit material that indeed enjoys full constitutional protection. This very consequence puts the court's rationale for the protection of material of this nature directly at issue.

4.2 Philosophical justification for freedom of expression: truth as political value

John Stuart Mill's marketplace of ideas paradigm53facilitates the argument that to suppress the expression of a view or opinion is regarded as harmful to the quest for the truth. Freedom of expression, to quote Hand J, "presupposes that right conclusions are more likely to be gathered out of a multitude of tongues, than through any kind of authoritative selection".54

Yet the First Amendment, like most clauses contained in a justiciable charter of fundamental rights, is by nature abstract and open-ended. The same holds true in respect of the Bill of Rights in the South African Constitution. In light of the abstract nature of the First Amendment (and absence of a general limitation clause), constitutional interpreters must seek a political justification for freedom of expression that not only corresponds with previous constitutional practice and precedents,55but also provides a compelling reason for granting this freedom such a privileged position among other liberties.

Mill's paradigm embraces two main justifications of the protection of freedom of expression. The first considers free speech as important instrumentally(i.e. the truth is more likely to be discovered and error eliminated if a free exchange of ideas and open debate is allowed, thus producing good political consequences);56the second views freedom of expression as an essential and constitutive feature of a just (liberal) political society which treats its (adult) members as responsible moral agents.57

The constitutive justification of free speech, in turn, encompasses two dimensions. The first dimension requires that morally responsible individuals make up their own minds about what is good or bad or true or false in life, politics or matters of justice, and thus the law should adopt a neutral attitude towards matters of life, sexuality and politics. But as Ronald Dworkin rightly contends, moral responsibility is thought to not only denote the shaping of one's own convictions, but also the conveying of those convictions to others so that the truth be known, justice be served and the common good be secured.58Consequently, when government forbids the expression of some social attitude or restricts political speech, it effectively violates the moral responsibility of its people. The instrumental and constitutive justifications of free expression are obviously not mutually exclusive and Mill indeed conceived of these as interrelated ideas.59

It follows, therefore, that if a court insists upon conducting its investigation into the extent to which sexually explicit material enjoys constitutional protection under the rubric of free speech, a court will have no option but to accommodate boththe idea that free speech is important to the discovery of truth and that it is an essential feature of a fair political dispensation. Yet the obscenity jurisprudence of the Supreme Court shows that the court only relies upon the instrumental justification of freedom of speech. Free speech is thus seen as essential in the quest for the truth and elimination of error in politics. The dicta in obscenity cases conclusively underscore this point: obscenity is thought to have "no redeeming social value";60to form "no essential part of any exposition of ideas"61and to lack "serious literary, artistic, political or scientific value".62

The possible constitutional consequences of the above justification of freedom of speech in relation to obscenity will be explored next.

 

5 An Instrumental Justification and its Constitutional Consequences

The reason why it has proved enormously difficult for United States courts (and the Supreme Court in particular) to distinguish obscenity from sexually explicit material that must have some redeeming value can be attributed squarely to the reliance on instrumental grounds as justification of freedom of expression. The Supreme Court has changed its mind about the ground of distinction so often and produced so many unworkable standards that Stewart J's frank declaration that he could not define obscenity but knew it when he saw it63has not surprisingly become the most quoted judicial pronouncement on the issue.64The intellectual basis that the Supreme Court employs for freedom of speech, coupled with the court's conception of "hard core pornography", thus becomes highly suspect.65

The categories employed by the Supreme Court whereby constitutionally protected speech is distinguished from unprotected obscenity seems highly arbitrary from the very perspective of the instrumental view of free speech that these categories are presumed to reflect. Consequently, the court's conception of obscenity can only be interpreted to the effect that the First Amendment must be understood to protect sexually explicit material on the forced (and easily rebuttable) assumption that citizens need such material in order to participate effectively in the political process. The First Amendment could thus be understood to protect nothing but political speech, and consequently, the protection afforded to literature, art and science can only be explained as a derivative from that principal political function.

Yet the instrumental justification of freedom of expression on its own cannot provide an intellectually acceptable justification for the First Amendment. The liberal argument that free speech is necessary if citizens are to be in command of their own political arrangementscould, for example, explain why a democratically elected government may not be allowed to resort to the secret censorship of sexually explicit material which citizens would reject if they were aware of its existence. But this does not explain why the majority of citizens should not be allowed to impose restrictions on sexually explicit material that they both approve of and indeed desire. If a distinction can be made between political and, for example, commercial speech (which the Supreme Court has firmly established enjoys much weaker protection),66then surely a distinction can also be made between racist or sexist speech and other forms of political comment and/or expression? This would enable the court to uphold legislative measures designed to prohibit political speech that violates the right to equality on grounds of race, sexual orientation, religion, sex, etc., as the instrumental justification of free speech would clearly offer little protection against a law designed with this political objective. This clearly shows that the Supreme Court finds itself in an untenable situation, since the instrumental premise of its analysis of obscenity actually serves to undermine the court's conception of a just and open political design.

Two critical consequences result from the Supreme Court's exclusion of obscenity from constitutional protection. On the one hand, the court has argued itself into a position where it can offer neither a constitutional nor philosophical basis on which to reject arguments for the regulation of all sexually explicit material. More particularly, the instrumental goal of a democratic and political order offers no challenge to a feminist argument that women are more effective participants in the political process when their fundamental rights and freedoms are not violated by the production and dissemination of gender-specific sexually explicit material. The court would therefore have no alternative but to agree that legislative measures which conceptualise such material as a violation of women's fundamental constitutional interests would enhance, rather than compromise, a democratic order, to the degree that these measures seek to restrict speech which decreases women's voice and role in the democratic political process.67

On the other hand, the Supreme Court can also provide neither a constitutional (nor philosophical) justification not to endorse the markedly different approach adopted by the Supreme Court of Canada on the issue of obscenity.68By employing an instrumental argument, the Canadian Supreme Court upheld a provision of the Canadian Criminal Code69which prohibits certain categories of sexually explicit material. Although the Supreme Court conceded that the effect of its decision was to narrow the scope of the right to freedom of expression guaranteed under section 2(b) of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms,70it maintained that sexually explicit material acutely offend the values fundamental to Canadian society. The Supreme Court thus found the restrictive effect of the Criminal Code on free expression justified, given the gravity of harm and the threat to the social and constitutional values at stake.

The distinct problems inherent to the particular conception of harm employed under the rubric of United States obscenity jurisprudence will be considered next.

 

6 Harm and Injury: The Supreme Court's Standard of Obscenity

The abstract liberal paradigm which the Supreme Court employs in its test for obscenity has led the court to embrace a restrictive conception of both harm and injury by requiring a direct causal link between speech and the alleged harm caused.

In the well known case of Brandenburg v The State of Ohio,71for example, the Supreme Court upheld the First Amendment rights of the Ku Klux Klan to publicly call for the expulsion of African Americans and Jews from society.72In determining the extent to which the state is permitted to forbid utterances of this nature, the Supreme Court held that the state may not proscribe advocacy of the use of force as a violation, except where such advocacy "is directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless action and is likely to incite or produce such action".73Subsequent to this decision, the Supreme Court has also rejected the notion that imminent and likely harm can be shown by linking a class of harm with a class of speech.74Since the Supreme Court requires that particular harm be directly related to particular speech, its conception of injury is likely to bear adversely on measures which seek to proscribe sexually explicit material.75Given that the Supreme Court's conception of harm demands evidence of a causal connection between speech and harm or injury, it requires a sophisticated theory of psychological causation as a prerequisite for statutory measures against material that would fall outside the ambit of the established standard of obscenity. This translates into a requirement of conclusive evidence that "non-hard core pornography" (i.e. material not deemed obscene) causes harm to women in that it transforms attitudes which translate into specific acts of (sexual) violence against women.

And yet United States courts are reluctant (and here the South African Constitutional Court follows suit)76to link violent material to evidence of sexual abuse. Social scientific studies that purport to show a correlation between sexually explicit material and instances of sexual violence against women77are dismissed by the courts as "very difficult to interpret"78and thus inconclusive. Since such material is assumed to constitute mere words and images, these cannot in themselves cause injury. And since it is required that harm must be direct, only sexually explicit material which directly incites the commitment of acts of imminent violence would be understood to "cause" harm, provided that actual injury occurs as a result.

The libertarian idea of injury has no way, therefore, of either conceptualising or recognising harm that does not cause direct (physical) injury or which advocates hate propaganda on the basis of race, ethnicity or gender. Consequently, the Supreme Court finds it especially difficult to conceive of non-violent sexually explicit material which contains degrading or dehumanising images of women as harmful. Research studies which found that material of this nature lower inhibitions, promote sexual aggression, increase the acceptance of women's sexual servitude and male dominance in intimate relationships79appear to have no persuasive force whatsoever. The Supreme Court would not, therefore, find it reasonable to conclude, as its Canadian counterpart has done,80that material of such a nature represents an appreciable risk of social harm, particularly to women and thus society as a whole.

The libertarian conception of harm, coupled with the test of obscenity articulated in Miller,indeed seem hard pressed to conceptualise sexually explicit material as a threat to women's constitutionally entrenched interests in equality, dignity, freedom from violence and physical integrity.

The definitive impact of United States obscenity jurisprudence on the thinking of the South African Constitutional Court will be critically examined next.

 

7 "Indecency", "Obscenity" and "Offensiveness": First Amendment Jurisprudence and the South African Constitutional Court

7.1 Case; Curtis v Minister of Safety and Security

The Constitutional Court's first (and to date only)81judgment on adult gender-specific sexually explicit material in Case; Curtis v Minister of Safety and Security82starkly reveals the dominant influence of United States obscenity jurisprudence in the South African constitutional context.83

In a judgment of less than three pages, the majority of the Constitutional Court84held that any ban on the possession of "erotic material"85for the solitary purpose of personal use invaded the right to privacy guaranteed under section 13 of the 1993 Constitution. In the words of Didcott J:

What erotic material I may choose to keep within the privacy of my home, and only for my personal use there, is nobody's business but mine . . . [i]t is certainly not the business of society or the State.86

In the present instance, the majority of the Constitutional Court found that the invasion of personal privacy was aggravated by the "preposterous definition"87of indecent or obscene photographic matter contained in section 1 of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Actwhich read:

Indecent or obscene matter includes photographic matter88or any part thereof depicting, displaying, exhibiting, manifesting, portraying or representing sexual intercourse, licentiousness, lust, homosexuality, lesbianism, masturbation, sexual assault, rape, sodomy, masochism, sadism, sexual bestiality or anything of a like nature.

The wide ambit of section 1 of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Actled the majority of the Constitutional Court to conclude that its scope inevitably also covered "reproductions of not a few famous works of art, ancient and modern, that are publicly displayed and can readily be viewed in major art galleries of the world".89The Constitutional Court therefore found it indisputable that section 2(1) of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Act90was in conflict with section 13 of the 1993 Constitution.

On the question whether section 2(1) of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Actwas also incompatible with the right to freedom of expression guaranteed under section 15 of the 1993 Constitution as alleged by the applicants,91the majority of the Constitutional Court felt that this question should "in the meantime . . . be left open", because once a violation of section 13 has been established, "there is no need to consider any alternative attack on section 2(1)" of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Act.92

The only issue that remained to be considered was whether section 33(1) of the 1993 Constitution which contained the general limitation clause, saved the prohibition contained in section 2(1) of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Actfrom nullification. Yet without alluding to, or even seeking to balance, the various interests at stake, the majority concluded that the intrusion into personal privacy that resulted from the prohibition contained in section 2(1) of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Actwas neither reasonable nor justifiable.93

Having found that section 2(1) of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Actinfringed section 13 of the 1993 Constitution and that this infringement was neither a reasonable nor justifiable limitation on the right to privacy, the majority directed their attention to the submissions made by several amici curiae, including People Opposing Women Abuse (POWA), the NICRO Women's Support Centre, the Advice Desk for Abused Women, Rape Crisis (Cape Town), the NISAA Institute for Women's Development and Women Abuse (WAWA) on the impact of sexually explicit material on the lives of women and the exploitation of women and children in, and through, such material. On the question whether violent forms of sexually explicit material have an impact on the incidence of sexual crimes against women, the majority of the Constitutional Court, in similar fashion to the United States Supreme Court, furnished a standard dismissive response and maintained the "the results of the research that was drawn to our attention neither prove nor disprove it empirically".94Yet in the very same paragraph, the majority observed that:

The production of pictures like those, and of future types equally depraved, is certainly an evil and may well deserve to be suppressed. Perhaps, as a means to an end, the same even goes for their possession, making it both reasonable and justifiable for society to mind the private business of its members.95

By contrast, Mokgoro J, in a separate judgment of more than thirty pages, sought to ascertain whether sexually explicit material would constitute a category of expressionprotected under section 15 of the 1993 Constitution and, if found to be the case, whether the possession of such material would accordingly also be subject to constitutional protection.96With direct reference to United States First Amendment jurisprudence, she argued that it was not to be simply assumed that the Interim Constitution protected sexually explicit material. In light of the general limitation clause contained in section 33 of the 1993 Constitution, she thus argued for a generous definition of the right to freedom of expression so as to include "non-political expression".97On the face of it, Mokgoro J argued, section 15 protected only expression and not the right to receive material generated and expressed by others. However, one's freedom of expression would be "impoverished indeed if it does not embrace also [the] right to receive, hold and consume expression transmitted by others".98By expressly embracing the free marketplace of ideas paradigm99and with reference to comparative case law,100Mokgoro J was impelled to conclude that so-called "sexually expressive speech" was subject to the protection of section 15 and that such protection must necessarily extend to the right to possess sexually explicit material.101

7.2 The perilous territory of privacy, moralistic condemnation and harm

A close reading of the Constitutional Court's judgment on the possible constitutional implications of adult gender-specific sexually explicit material reveals a distinctly libertarian and moralistic understanding of both the constitutional mould within which such a debate ought to be cast as well as the actual impact of such material on women's constitutional interests in equality, dignity and physical integrity. The Constitutional Court's assessment thus raises a number of concerns, the majority of which emanate from the prioritization of the right to privacy, thereby misconstruing the ensuing (constitutional) harm, coupled with the use of imprecise (even contradictory) terminology and the deliberate avoidance of formulating a working (legal) definition of the type of material under constitutional scrutiny.

7.2.1 The constitutional priority: privacy, not gender-specific harm

The Constitutional Court's endorsement of a libertarian argument is nowhere more clearly illustrated than in its decision to frame the issue before it exclusively as one concerning the (individual's) right to privacy. Consequently, the constitutional implications of section 2(1) of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Actare unavoidably balanced against the interests, liberties and rights of the individual. The core tenets of liberal philosophy, notably individual sovereignty, (moral) freedom and privacy thus become elevated to present unqualified constitutional values, prioritised over other fundamental and significant constitutional values, most notably equality, human dignity and physical integrity. The Constitutional Court thus appears to subscribe to the liberal political assumption that the demarcation between the public and the private sphere is sound and seems completely unaware of the possibility that the private sphere, in which the individual is free to exercise all moral choices, could be construed as a seat of oppression and exploitation, manifesting in the physical, emotional and sexual abuse of women.102Consequently, women's experiences of sexual violence occurring in the private domain are overshadowed, even silenced, and thus the real harm is overlooked and/or misconstrued. The real harm is not, therefore, to be found in the curtailment of the individual's right to privacy, but in the fact that both the existence and the (violent) impact of patriarchal power and entrenched male privilege are rendered invisible in the private sphere. Gender-specific sexual violence is thus all too readily reduced to an arbitrary and indiscriminate individualincident,103all as a direct consequence of the fact that female sexuality, both expressed and conceptualised in the creation, use and dissemination of sexually explicit material, is understood as a matter exclusive to the private sphere where the individual is to remain undisturbed so as to freely exercise all moral choices.104The remark by Sachs J that "[i]t seems strange that what one can do in the privacy of one's bedroom one cannot look at in one's bedroom"105appears completely unaware of the fact that the private sphere is a seat of male privilege, manifesting in gender-specific oppression, subjugation and harm.106The Constitutional Court's libertarian justification for, and constitutional protection accorded to, adult gender-specific sexually explicit material is thus indeed cause for concern.

Moreover, the Constitutional Court's almost blunt refusal to accept social scientific studies that argue for a correlation between violent sexually explicit material and the commission of sexual crimes against women "and other socially repulsive behavior"107further illustrate the pervasive influence of United States obscenity jurisprudence.108It is not surprising, therefore, when the majority of the Constitutional Court first rejects the research as not "definitive",109yet thereafter, in the identical paragraph, admits that the "production of pictures like those, and of further types of equally depraved, is certainly an evil and may well deserve to be suppressed".110The particular problems raised by the failure of the majority of the Constitutional Court to conceptualise the type of material under scrutiny will be examined next.

7.2.2 Defining pornography: free expression premised upon a moralistic condemnation?

Although the majority of the Constitutional Court shied away from explaining the precise meaning of the words "erotic material"111(even though it was expressly held that such material would enjoy constitutional protection), the majority appeared quite unaware of the distinct meaning that these words enjoy within (radical) feminist discourse.112Only Mokgoro J, under the rubric of First Amendment jurisprudence, bravely attempted to conceptualise the type of material proscribed by section 1 of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Actas "sexually explicit expression"113and "sexually expressive speech".114None of the other members of the Constitutional Court ventured anywhere near to proposing a working definition. And yet the conclusions reached by the Constitutional Court invariably imply that its members must have embraced some definition or other. The vocabulary favoured by Didcott J is telling: "repulsive behavior", "evil", "depraved", "obnoxious" and "unbearably vile pictures"115point towards a distinctly libertarian and moralistic conception (and censure) of the matter under consideration.

And yet the Constitutional Court appears wholly unaware of the fact that a libertarian, moralistic condemnation of sexually explicit material unavoidably conceptualises it as a mode of expression which appeals to the "prurient interest" and which must be assessed, rather inescapably, with explicit reference to the likes and dislikes of the "average [male] person" against the background of "contemporary community standards".116Moreover, the Constitutional Court seems painfully unaware of the fact that since it is not the principal concern of a moralistic condemnation to safeguard the advancement of women (be it legally, socially or politically), such a conception stands in direct opposition to viewing the matter as a possible violation of women's constitutional interests in equality, dignity and physical integrity. These fundamental constitutional concerns are far removed indeed from a position which regards such material in relation to the measure of revulsion or distaste that it is considered to provoke.

 

8 Concluding Observations

This article examined critically the particular understanding of adult gender-specific sexually explicit material emerging from the jurisprudence of the United States Supreme Court, the apparent uncritical endorsement thereof in South African constitutional thought, and argued that First Amendment jurisprudence is wholly insensitive to the possible gender-specific constitutional harm which may result from an abstract liberal-inspired accommodation of sexually explicit material in an imagined free and open democratic society.

Mindful of the fact that freedom of expression is characteristically valued on the basis that it advances the discovery of the truth, the individual search for autonomy (and self-fulfilment), and participation in the democratic process and its structures,117the article has shown that the instrumental justification of freedom of expression is inherently flawed. And yet the South African Constitutional Court has explicitly recognised this philosophical justification as the basis for free speech and expression. The Constitutional Court has, in fact, both supported and emphasised the idea that freedom of expression stands central to the concepts of democracy and political transformation through participation,118and has expressly confirmed the association between freedom of expression and the political rights safeguarded under the Bill of Rights.119

And yet by embracing a moralistic, libertarian model of free expression in relation to sexually explicit material, the very ideal of a free, democratic and equal society, one in which women can live secure from the threat of harm, is put at risk. A moralistic, libertarian model is simply not capable of conceptualising such material as a possible violation of women's fundamental interests in equality, dignity and physical integrity. Far from it being a case of "fettering ourselves with premature decisions", it remains imperative for the Constitutional Court to critically engage with the consequences of adopting First Amendment jurisprudence into South African constitutional discourse. For the constitutional debate on gender, sexually explicit material and harm is far from settled and remains, in the words of Didcott J, an "important and contentious issue".120

 

Bibliography

Books

Bronstein V "The Rape Complainant in Court: An Analysis of Legal Discourse" in Murray C (ed) Gender and the New South African Legal Order (Juta & Co Ltd Kenwyn 1994) 202-227        [ Links ]

Clark L "Liberalism and Pornography" in Copp W (ed) Pornography and Censorship (Prometheus New York 1983) 50-62        [ Links ]

Currie I and De Waal J "Expression" in I Currie and J de Waal The Bill of Rights Handbook 5ed (2005) 358-394        [ Links ]

Hoffmann LH and Zeffertt D "Sufficiency of Evidence" in LH Hoffmann and D Zeffert The South African Law of Evidence (1988) 566 at 579-580        [ Links ]

MacKinnon CA Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law (Harvard University Press Cambridge 1987)        [ Links ]

MacKinnon CA Toward a Feminist Theory of the State (Harvard University Press Cambridge 1989)        [ Links ]

MacKinnon CA Only Words (Harvard University Press Cambridge 1993)        [ Links ]

MacKinnon CA and Dworkin A (eds) In Harm's Way: The Pornography Civil Rights Hearings (Harvard University Press Cambridge 1997)        [ Links ]

Morris A "International reform initiatives regarding violence against women: successes and pitfalls" in Jagwanth S, Schwikkard P and Grant B (eds) Women and the Law (HSRC Publishers Pretoria 1994) 351-380        [ Links ]

Pateman C "Feminist Critiques of the Public/Private Dichotomy" in Phillips A (ed) Feminism and Equality (New York University Press New York 1987) 91-118        [ Links ]

Schauer F "The American Approach to the Law of Obscenity" in Duncan J (ed) Between Speech and Silence: Hate Speech, Pornography and the new South Africa (The Freedom of Expression Institute and The Institute for Democracy in South Africa Johannesburg 1996) 68        [ Links ]

Van der Westhuizen J "Freedom of Expression" in Van Wyk D et al Rights and Constitutionalism: The New South African Legal Order (Juta & Co Ltd Kenwyn 1996) 264-291        [ Links ]

Van Marle K and Bonthuys E "Feminist Theories and Concepts" in Bonthuys E and Albertyn (eds) Gender, Law and Justice (Juta & Co Ltd Cape Town 2007) 15-50        [ Links ]

Zillmann D and Bryant J "Effects of Massive Exposure to Pornography" in Malamuth NM and Donnerstein E (eds) Pornography and Sexual Aggression (Women's Press London 1984) 130-131        [ Links ]

Zillmann D and Weaver JB "Pornography and Men's Sexual Callousness Towards Women" in Malamuth NM and Donnerstein E (eds) Pornography and Sexual Aggression (Women's Press London 1984) 95-125        [ Links ]

Journal articles

CE Baker "Scope of the First Amendment Freedom of Speech" (1978) Vol 25 University of California Los Angeles Law Review 964        [ Links ]

Baker CE "The Process of Change and the Liberty of the First Amendment" 1982 55 Southern California Law Review 293        [ Links ]

Check JVP and Malamuth NM "Pornography and Sexual Aggression: A Social Learning Theory Analysis" 1989 9 Communication Year Book 74        [ Links ]

R Dworkin "Is there a Right to Pornography?" 1981 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 177        [ Links ]

K Lahey "The Canadian Charter of Rights and Pornography: Toward a Theory of Actual Gender Equality" (1984-1985) Vol 20 No 4 New England Law Review 649        [ Links ]

Linz D et al "The Effects of Multiple Exposures to Filmed Violence Against Women" 1984 34 Journal of Communication 130        [ Links ]

Lindgren J "Defining Pornography" (1993) Vol 141 No 4 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 1156        [ Links ]

Malamuth NM and Check JVP "Penile Tumescence and Perceptual Responses to Rape as a Function of the Victim's Perceived Reactions" 1980 10 Journal of Applied Psychology 528        [ Links ]

Russell DEH "Pornography and Rape: A Causal Model" 1988 9 Political Psychology 41        [ Links ]

Scanlon T "A Theory of Freedom of Expression" 1972 1 Philosophy and Public Affairs 204        [ Links ]

Scanlon T "Freedom of Expression and Categories of Expression" 1979 40 University of Pittsburgh Law Review 519        [ Links ]

Van der Poll L "Pornography as Sex Discrimination? A Critical Reflection on the Constitutional Court's Interpretation of Gender Politics, Differentiation and (Unfair) Discrimination" (2010) Vol 21 No 3 Stellenbosch Law Review 381        [ Links ]

Zillmann D and Bryant J "Effects of Prolonged Consumption of Pornography on Family Values" 1988 9 Journal of Family Issues 518        [ Links ]

Register of cases

Abrams v United States 250 US 616 (1919)

Adams Theatre Co v Keenan 12 J 267 (1953)

American Booksellers Association Inc v Hudnut 771 F2d 323 7thCir (1985)

American Civil Liberties Union v Chicago 3 Ill2d 334 (1955)

Banana v Attorney-General 1999 1 BCLR 27 (ZS)

Bantam Books Inc v Melko 25 NJ Super 292 (1953)

Beauharnais v The State of Illinois 343 US 250 (1952)

Breard v Alexandria 341 US 622 (1951)

Case; Curtis v Minister of Safety and Security1996 5 BCLR 609 (CC)

Central Hudson Gas v Public Service Commission 447 US 557 (1980)

CF Griggs v Duke Power Company 410 US 424 (1971)

Chaplinsky v New Hampshire 315 US 568 (1942)

Commonwealth v Buckley 200 Mass 346 86 NE 910 (1909)

Commonwealth v Gordon 66 Pa D&C 10 (1949)

Commonwealth v Holmes 17 Mass 335 (1821)

Commonwealth v Isenstadt 318 Mass 543 (1945)

Commonwealth v Sharpless 2 Serg & R 91; 7 Am Dec 632 (Pa 1815)

De Reuck v Director of Public Prosecutions (Witwatersrand Local Division) 2004 1 SA 406 (CC)

Ex parte Jackson 96 US 727 (1877)

Gaston County v United States 395 US 285 (1969)

Ginzberg v New York 390 US 629 (1968)

Gregg v The State of Georgia 428 US 153 (1976)

Hannegan v Esquire Inc 327 US 146 (1946)

Hess v The State of Indiana 414 US 105 (1973)

Hoke v United States 227 US 308 (1913)

Interstate Circuit Inc v Dallas 390 US 676 (1968)

Jacobellis v The State of Ohio 378 US 184 (1964)

Joseph Burstyn Inc v Wilson 343 US 495 (1952)

Kahn v Leo Feist Inc (DC NY) 70 F Supp 4 (1947)

Kauesa v Minister of Home Affairs 1995 11 BCLR 1540 (NmS)

Knowles v State 3 Day 103 9Conn (1808)

Kois v Wisconsin 408 US 229 (1972)

Kovacs v Cooper 336 US 77 (1949)

Memoirs v Attorney General of Massachusetts383 US 413 (1966)

Miller v California413 US 15 (1973)

Missouri v Becker 364 Mo 1079 (1954)

Near v The State of Minnesota 28 US 697 (1931)

Paris Adult Theatre I et al v Lewis R Slaton, District Attorney, Atlanta Judicial Circuit, et al 413 US 49 (1973)

Parmelee v United States 72 App DC 203 (1940)

Prince v The State of Massachusetts 321 US 158 (1944)

Public Clearing House v Coyne 194 US 497 (1904)

Rabe v Washington 405 US 313 (1972)

Redrup v New York 386 US 767 (1967)

Regina v Butler[1992] 1 SCR 452

Regina v Hicklin (1868) LR 3 QB 360

Regina v Ramsingh (1984) 14 CCC (3d) 230

Regina v Wagner (1985) 43 CR (ed) 318 (Alta QB)

Robertson v Baldwin 165 US 275 (1897)

Roth v United States 354 US 476 (1957)

South African National Defence Force Union v Minister of Defence 1999 4 SA 469 (CC)

Stanley v The State of Georgia 394 US 557 (1969)

The State of Oregon v Mitchell 400 US 112 (1970)

Towne Cinema Theatres Ltd v The Queen [1985] 1 SCR 494

Valentine v Christensen 316 US 52 (1942)

Virginia Pharmacy Bd v Virginia Consumer Council 425 US 748 (1976)

United States v Bennett (CC NY) 16 Blatchf 338 (1879)

United States v Chase 135 US 255 (1890)

United States v Clarke (DC Mo) 38 F 500 (1889)

United States v Dennett (CA NY) 39 F2d 564 (1930)

United States v Kennerley (DC NY) 209 F 119 (1913)

United States v One Book Called "Ulysses" (DC NY) F Supp 182 (1933)

United States v Reidel 402 US 351 (1971)

Walker v Popenoe 80 App DC 129 (1957)

Whitney v The State of California 274 US 357 (1927)

Winters v The State of New York 333 US 507 (1948)

Newspaper reports

Dworkin R "Women and Pornography" The New York Review 21 October 1993

Register of legislation

Act Concerning Crimes and Punishmentsof 1821 (United States)

Act for Suppressing Vice and Immoralityof 1798 (United States)

Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germanyof 1949

Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Constitution Actof 1982 Part I

Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act 200 of 1993

Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996

Criminal CodeRSC C-46 of 1985 (Canada)

Films and Publications Act65 of 1996

Films and Publications Amendment Act34 of 1999

Films and Publications Amendment Act18 of 2004

Human Rights Act54 of 1994

Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Act37 of 1967

Model Penal Code Tenth Draft 6 of 1957 (United States)

New Jersey Revised Laws329 of 1800

Obscene Publications Act20 & 21 Vict c83 of 1857 (United Kingdom)

Prevention and Combating of Corrupt Activities Act12 of 2004

Revised Statuteof 1835 (United States)

Revised Statute of 1842 (United States)

Revised Statute of Massachusetts740 of 1836

Revised Statute of New Hampshire221 of 1843

Statutory Laws of Connecticut109 of 1824

Register of government publications

Government Gazette 20837 of 4 February 2000

South African Human Rights Commission Interim Report: Media Inquiry of 21 November 1999

Register of other reports

"Institutional Hearing: The Media" TRC Report (1998) 165-180;

Addison G "Censorship of the Press in South Africa During the Angolan War: A Case Study of News Manipulation and Suppression" TRC Report (1998) 165-182

"A Submission from the South African Union of Journalists to the TRC concerning the Role of the Media during the Apartheid Years" TRC Report 166. 

Register of internet sources

Bischof J Debate on media tribunal hots up www.journalism.co.za [date of use 12 Jun 2011]        [ Links ]

Duncan J The prevention of scholarship bill http://www.universityworldnews.com/article [date of use 12 Jun 2011]        [ Links ]

Republic of South Africa Protection of Information Bill (as introduced by the Minister of Intelligence (National Assembly)) BXX-2008 5 March 2008 http://www.iss.co.za/uploads/POIBILL.PDF[date of use 12 Jun 2011]        [ Links ]

Section27 The Protection of Information Bill is unconstitutional and anti-democratic http://www.mail&guardian.com [date of use 12 Jun 2011]        [ Links ]

List of abbreviations

 

 

 

1 Per Sachs J in Case; Curtis v Minister of Safety and Security 1996 5 BCLR 609 (CC) par [108].
2 MacKinnon Feminist Theory 196. Emphasis added.
3 "Adult" signifies that the material must be both directed at persons who are eighteen years or older and must involve (or depict) persons who are eighteen years or older.
4 "Gender-specific" denotes that the material in question, through the medium of pictures (including films, photographs, sketches or prints) or sexually explicit words and prose, contain images of adult (heterosexual) women. See also n 6.
5 Adult gender-specific sexually explicit material is, for present purposes, understood to consist of sexually explicit images, irrespective of how created, of adult women specifically produced for, and consumed by, the adult male heterosexual market, to be set apart, therefore, from so-called "child", "gay" and "lesbian" pornography. This genre of pornography could thus well be termed "adult heterosexual pornography": see, in particular, Van der Poll 2010 Stell LR 387. See also n 11 and n 12.
6 For a comprehensive discussion of the success of various attempts at formulating a legal definition of sexually explicit material in Anglo-American jurisprudence, see Lindgren 1993 U Pa L Rev 1156.
7 These hermeneutical "parameters" are fundamental to the interpretation of the possible constitutional implications of the material under consideration.
8 See, in particular, n 54.
9 See, in particular, par 7.1 n 121.
10 S 1 of the Films and Publications Act 65 of 1996 (as amended by the Films and Publications Amendment Act 34 of 1999, the Films and Publications Amendment Act 18 of 2004 and the Prevention and Combating of Corrupt Activities Act 12 of 2004) defines "child pornography" as "any image, however, created, or any description of a person, real or simulated, who is, or who is depicted or described as being, under the age of 18 years - (i) engaged in sexual conduct; (ii) participating in, or assisting another person to participate in, sexual conduct; or (iii) showing or describing the body, or parts of the body, of such a person in a manner or in circumstances which, within context, amounts to sexual exploitation, or in such a manner that it is capable of being used for the purpose of sexual exploitation." This definition was inserted into the Films and Publications Act 65 of 1996 by s 1(a) of the Films and Publications Amendment Act 34 of 1999, and substituted by s 1(a) of the Films and Publications Amendment Act 18 of 2004.
11 For present purposes, the terms "gay" and "lesbian" pornography refer to graphic sexually explicit images, irrespective of how created, of adult men and women specifically produced for, and consumed by, the adult gay and lesbian market.
12 Obscene Publications Act 20 & 21 Vict c83 of 1857. Its chief architect, Lord Campbell, articulated the purpose of the Act during a session of the British Parliament as follows: "[t]he measure was intended to apply exclusively to works written for the single purpose of corrupting the morals of youth and of a nature calculated to shock common feelings of decency in a well-regulated mind".
13 (1868) LR 3 QB 360.
14 In the words of Cockburn CJ 371: "I think the test of obscenity is this, whether the tendency of the matter charged as obscenity is to deprave and corrupt those whose minds are open to such immoral influences, and into whose hands a publication of this sort may fall".
15 See, for example, United States v Kennerley (DC NY) 209 F 119 (1913); United States v Bennett (CC NY) 16 Blatchf 338 (1879); United States v Clarke (DC Mo) 38 F 500 (1889); and Commonwealth v Buckley 200 Mass 346 86 NE 910 (1909). The Hicklin standard was only abandoned in the late 1950s: see, inter alia, Walker v Popenoe 80 App DC 129 (1957); Parmelee v United States 72 App DC 203 (1940); United States v Dennett (CA NY) 39 F2d 564 (1930); Kahn v Leo Feist Inc (DC NY) 70 F Supp 4 (1947); United States v One Book Called "Ulysses" (DC NY) F Supp 182 (1933); American Civil Liberties Union v Chicago 3 Ill2d 334 (1955); Commonwealth v Isenstadt 318 Mass 543 (1945); Missouri v Becker 364 Mo 1079 (1954); Adams Theatre Co v Keenan 12 J 267 (1953); Bantam Books Inc v Melko 25 NJ Super 292 (1953); and Commonwealth v Gordon 66 Pa D&C 10 (1949).
16 The First Amendment (which was added to the Constitution in 1791) reads: "Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress of grievances". Emphasis added.
17 354 US 476 (1957).
18 413 US 15 (1973).
19 485. Emphasis added.
20 See, in particular, Chaplinsky v New Hampshire 315 US 568 (1942) 568.
21 485. Even though it was now established by the Supreme Court that obscenity deserves no constitutional protection, Brennan J nevertheless still had to determine whether a clear and present danger must exist before obscenity is punishable by law. In an attempt to resolve this issue, he relied on Beauharnais v The State of Illinois 343 US 250 (1952) where the Supreme Court held that if utterances are not within the areas of constitutionally protected speech, it becomes unnecessary for the court to consider whether these present a clear and present danger, in light of this precedent, Brennan J did not, therefore, find it necessary to first show that obscene materials create a clear and present danger of, for example, anti-social conduct before these may be punishable by state or federal law.
22 487.
23 Per Harlan J (concurring and dissenting) in Interstate Circuit Inc v Dallas 390 US 676 (1968) 704-705.
24 In A Book Named "John Cleland's Memoirs of a Woman of Pleasure" v Attorney General of Massachusetts 383 US 413 (1966) 418, popularly known as Memoirs v Massachusetts.
25 In Interstate Circuit Inc v Dallas 390 US 676 (1968) 704.
26 Marvin Miller conducted a mass mailing campaign to advertise the sale of illustrated books under the genre of "adult" material. After a jury trial in a California State Court, the defendant was convicted of a misdemeanor in violation of para 311 subpara 311.2(a) of the California Penal Code (as amended) for the distribution of five unsolicited advertising brochures through the mail to a restaurant in Newport Beach. The unsolicited package was opened by the restaurant manager who subsequently lodged a complaint with the police. The brochure, which advertised four books and a film respectively entitled Intercourse, Man-Woman, Sex Orgies Illustrated, An Illustrated History of Pornography and Marital Intercourse, consisted primarily of explicit pictures and drawings depicting men and women in groups of two or more engaging in a variety of sexual activities with genitals often prominently displayed. The Appellate Department of the Superior Court of California (Orange County) summarily affirmed the judgment without opinion: see 37 L Ed 2d 419 (1973). The matter was subsequently reviewed by the Supreme Court.
27 That is, since its 1942 decision in Chaplinsky v New Hampshire 315 US 568 (1942).
28 A particular category of pornographic material, which the court set forth to define, was included under so-called "obscene expression" in a footnote of Burger CJ's opinion 18 n 2.
29 27.
30 29.
31 The third prong of the standard enunciated in Memoirs v Attorney General of Massachusetts 383 US 413 (1966) was expressly rejected by Burger CJ 24.
32 31.
33 19.
34 Miller v California (n 19) 487.
35 20.
36 Kois v Wisconsin 408 US 229 (1972) 230, quoting Roth v United States 354 US 476 (1957) 489.
37 24. Emphasis in the original. The scope of this article precludes a detailed assessment of the Supreme Court's three-part standard of obscenity. And yet this standard is itself problematic for various reasons. These relate to the inherently subjective nature of the test (highlighted by the fact that the work must appeal to the "prurient interest", indicating that tastes and attitudes are to be elevated to a constitutional standard as prurience could well be said to be the lowest common denominator of sexually explicit material); its moralistic premise (highlighted by the fact that the work must be "patently offensive", thus misconstruing the harm of pornography by seeing it as an assault against the good moral social order); and lack of clarity regarding the precise meaning of key terms (particularly evident in the requirement that the work must lack "serious literary, artistic, political, or scientific value"). If "serious" is to be construed to mean bona fide, publications which combine graphic sexual explicitness with lifestyle articles on, for example, décor, leisure and cuisine would raise obvious difficulties. Since these articles have some "redeeming social importance" (per Brennan J in Roth 485), the publication is unlikely - when "taken as a whole" (per Burger J in Miller 24) - to fall foul of the Supreme Court's obscenity standard. In the United States, Playboy and Hustler magazines are not deemed legally obscene for precisely this reason and these two publications have managed to bask in, and indeed flourish under, the protection of the First Amendment.
38 30. The judgment of the court a quo was thus set aside and the case was remanded to that court for further proceedings consistent with the new standard established by the Supreme Court's opinion.
39 Per Burger CJ 29.
40 The furor surrounding the painting by artist Brett Murray named "The Spear" depicting President Jacob Zuma in a pose that is reminiscent of Wiktor Iwanof's propagandist poster of Wladimir Lenin, but with his genitals prominently exposed, underscores this point. In approaching the South Gauteng High Court for an urgent interdict against City Press and the Goodman Gallery to ban all depictions of the painting, the ANC argued, inter alia, that the painting was racist in its depiction of African sexuality in general and African men in particular.
41 For centuries under patriarchal rule, the testimony of a woman who alleges rape or indecent assault was subjected to the cautionary rule in the Anglo-American system of evidence. As in the case of children, the testimony furnished by a female complainant in sexual proceedings had to be viewed with suspicion and approached with caution. Her testimony was thought to raise particular problems of corroboration even though the danger of a false charge would ultimately be balanced by the normal incidence of the onus which serves to protect the accused in criminal proceedings. For more on the historical context of the cautionary rule in the Anglo-American system of evidence, see, in general, Hoffmann and Zeffertt Law of Evidence 579-580.
42 It is a historical fact that the First Amendment, together with its values of individuality, autonomy and neutrality, existed in harmony with both institutionalised slavery and (racial) segregation. No effective challenge to these two systems of racial subordination was ever mounted under the rubric of free expression, even though literacy tests were used in the United States to screen the eligibility of voters: see, for example, The State of Oregon v Mitchell 400 US 112 (1970) at 132-133. Since segregated separate-but-equal-education assured that African Americans remained vastly illiterate, they had no reasonable opportunity to meet the literacy requirements in order to participate in a fundamental part of the political process. See also, in general, Gaston County v United States 395 US 285 (1969); CF Griggs v Duke Power Company 410 US 424 (1971); and Baker 1982 S Cal L Rev 293.
43 See MacKinnon and Dworkin (eds) In Harm's Way 319.
44 The South African Human Rights Commission formally resolved to conduct an investigation into racism in the media at its twenty-sixth Plenary Session held on 11 November 1998. The inquiry was conducted in terms of s 184(2)(a) of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996.
45 The Interim Report of the Human Rights Commission (dated 21 November 1999) presents an overview of the various submissions received by the Commission as well as the results of the research that it commissioned. The Interim Report invited responses from both interested parties and those "adversely affected by what is contained in this report": see SAHRC Interim Report 1. Subsequent to the publication of this Report, public hearings were held in terms of s 15 of the Human Rights Act 54 of 1994: see GG 20837 of 4 February 2000 44.
46 Submissions before the South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission highlighted how the South African media were both used and structured to promote white male supremacy: see TRC Report 1998 165-181; Addison TRC Report 1998 182; and TRC Report 1998 166.
47 The Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, Act 200 of 1993, which entered into force on 27 April 1994.
48 See, in particular, Lahey 1984-1985 New Eng L Rev 652.
49 See Republic of South Africa Protection of Information Bill (as introduced by the Minister of Intelligence (National Assembly)) BXX-2008 5 March 2008 http://www.iss.co.za/uploads/ POIBILL.PDF 12 June 2011.
50 The idea of a tribunal was first raised at the conference of the African National Congress (the ANC) held in Polokwane, Limpopo, in 2007. It reappeared in 2010 as a working paper for the ANC's National General Council. In essence, the ANC proposed that a tribunal should oversee complaints brought against the press, instead of continuing with the industry practice of self-regulation. The ANC reassured the media that the tribunal would function independently from government and that the tribunal would respect the constitutional guarantees pertaining to media freedom. Various interest groups, including the South African Civil Society Information Service, various newspaper editors and some schools of journalism (notably at Rhodes University and the University of the Witwatersrand), have vehemently criticised the ANC's proposal. See, in general, Bischof 2011 http://www.journalism.co.za 12 June 2011.
51 Both the Republic of South Africa Protection of Information Bill and proposals for the creation of a Media Tribunal have been met with vehement opposition from, inter alia, the Right2Know Campaign, the Treatment Action Campaign and Section27. These interest groups have called for the Republic of South Africa Protection of Information Bill to be amended to: (a) limit secrecy to core state bodies in the security sector, such as the police, defence and intelligence agencies; (b) limit secrecy to strictly defined national security matters, insisting that officials must give reasons for making information secret; (c) not exempt the intelligence agencies from public scrutiny; (d) not apply penalties for unauthorised disclosure to society at large, but only to those responsible for keeping secrets; (e) make provision for an independent body to be appointed by Parliament, and not the Minister of State Security, to act as the arbiter of decisions about what information may be classified as secret, whose decisions should be subject to review by the courts; and (f) not criminalise the legitimate disclosure of secrets in the public interest. See, in general, Section27 http://www.mail&guardian.com 12 June 2011 and Duncan http://www.universityworldnews.com/article 12 June 2011.
52 See, in particular, par 3 and n 38.
53 Mill's open marketplace of ideas metaphor was developed in the second chapter of his essay on the struggle between liberty and authority entitled On Liberty, first published in 1859. In this chapter, Mill employs the so-called negative idea of liberty in his examination of freedom of opinion and of the press. Negative liberty is based on two key assumptions, namely that speech will naturally be free provided the state does not restrain it, and secondly, that the important issue is the avoidance of restrictions on speech rather than affirmative access to speech for those to whom it has been denied historically. Constitutional rights and interests are thus interpreted in relation to state action and the guarantee of liberty is interpreted to exist to the extent that there is no state interference. The idea of negative liberty has subsequently become entrenched as a cornerstone of the modern liberal state.
54 See United States Associated Press 52 F Supp 362 at 372, cited in New York Times v Sullivan 376 US 254 (1964).
55 See, in general, Schauer American Approach to Obscenity 68.
56 See, in particular, Mill On Liberty 76-77.
57 See, in general, Van der Westhuizen Freedom of Expression 267-273 and Dworkin 1981 OJLS 178-179, 194-199. See also Abrams v United States 250 US 616 (1919) and Whitney v The State of California 274 US 357 (1927).
58 The underlying assumption is thus that citizens have as much right to contribute to the establishment of the moral or aesthetic climate as they do to participate in politics: see, in particular, Dworkin 1981 OJLS 184.
59 As did Brandeis J in a dissenting opinion in Whitney v The State of California 274 US 357 (1927). See also Scanlon 1972 Philos Public Aff 204 where he developed a Kantian argument for the constitutive justification of freedom of expression and 1979 U Pitt L Rev 519 where Scanlon emphasises the complex character of an account of the right to free speech and indeed concluded that instrumental and constitutive factors must both feature in a theoretical justification of free expression.
60 See Memoirs v Attorney General of Massachusetts 383 US 413 (1966) 418.
61 In Chaplinsky v New Hampshire 315 US 568 (1942) 571.
62 In Miller v California 413 US 15 (1973) 24.
63 In Jacobellis v The State of Ohio 378 US 184 (1964) 197.
64 This pronouncement has also found favour with the South African Constitutional Court in Case; Curtis v Minister of Safety and Security 1996 5 BCLR 609 (CC) par [108].
65 Dworkin rightly observes that "[l]iberals defending a right to pornography find themselves triply on the defensive: their view is politically weak, deeply offensive to many women, and intellectually doubtful": see NY Rev 21 October 1993. Brennan J's change of course in Paris Adult Theatre I et al v Lewis R Slaton, District Attorney, Atlanta Judicial Circuit, et al 413 US 49 (1973) could possibly be seen as an attempt to reconcile his new view (namely that the United States Constitution prohibits government from suppressing obscenity except in the case of non-consenting adults and minors) with the instrumental justification of free speech. Had Brennan J more clearly recognized the constitutive justification of free speech when the court was first called upon to consider the issue, he would undoubtedly have been in a much stronger position to formulate a persuasive constitutional argument against hard core pornography.
66 See Virginia Pharmacy Bd v Virginia Consumer Council 425 US 748 (1976). Prior to 1976, United States constitutional jurisprudence viewed most kinds of commercial speech as an unprotected category situated outside of the scope of the First Amendment: see Valentine v Christensen 316 US 52 (1942). For an exposition of the criteria employed by the Supreme Court to determine whether the regulation of commercial speech violates the First Amendment, see Central Hudson Gas v Public Service Commission 447 US 557 (1980).
67 Easterbrook J's rejection of this feminist strategy in American Booksellers Association Inc v Hudnut 771 F2d 323 7th Cir (1985) indeed shows that he parted ways with the Supreme Court's justification of free speech and tacitly relied on the constitutive rather than the instrumental justification of freedom of expression.
68 In Regina v Butler [1992] 1 SCR 452.
69 Section 163(8) of the Criminal Code RSC C-46 of 1985 (Canada).
70 Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Constitution Act of 1982 Part I.
71 395 US 444 (1969).
72 446.
73 447. Emphasis added.
74 See Hess v The State of Indiana 414 US 105 (1973). In this case, the Supreme Court overturned a conviction for disorderly conduct on the basis that the defendant's speech was neither directed toward a particular person nor intended to incite a specific act of violence.
75 107-109. This consequence was expressly affirmed by the Federal District Court in respect of pornography. The court held that the forms of expression defined as pornography under the anti-pornography ordinance for Indianapolis did not "by their very nature carry the immediate potential for injury": see American Booksellers Association Inc v Hudnut 771 F2d 323 7th Cir (1985) 1331.
76 In Case; Curtis v Minister of Safety and Security 1996 5 BCLR 609 (CC) par [93].
77 See, for example, Linz et al 1984 J Commun 142 (documenting that men exposed to filmed violence against women judged a rape victim to be less injured than did the control group); Malamuth and Check 1980 J Appl Psychol 542-543 (documenting that exposure to rape depictions affected future reactions to rape). See also n 106.
78 Per Easterbrook J in American Booksellers Association Inc v Hudnut 771 F2d 323 7th Cir (1985) n 2, citing Gregg v The State of Georgia 428 US 153 (1976) 184-187.
79 See, in particular, Check and Malamuth 1989 Commun Yearb 74; Russell 1988 Polit Psychol 41; Zillmann and Bryant 1988 J Fam Issues 518; Zillmann and Bryant Massive Exposure 130-131; and Zillmann and Weaver Sexual Callousness 95.
80 In Regina v Butler [1992] 1 SCR 452. See also Regina v Wagner (1985) 43 CR (ed) 318 (Alta QB); Regina v Ramsingh (1984) 14 CCC (3d) 230; and Towne Cinema Theatres Ltd v The Queen [1985] 1 SCR 494.
81 The subsequent decision of the Constitutional Court in De Reuck v Director of Public Prosecutions (Witwatersrand Local Division) 2004 1 SA 406 (CC) concerned the constitutional ramifications of so-called "child" pornography which falls beyond the scope of this article. See also n 9.
82 1996 5 BCLR 609 (CC).
83 This judgment concerned the simultaneous adjudication of the matters of Patrick and Inge Case and Stephen Roy Curtis who had been arraigned before the Randburg Magistrates' Court on charges of possession of sexually explicit video material in contravention of s 2(1) of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Act 37 of 1967. After a number of appearances in the Magistrates' Court, the Case applicants lodged an application in terms of s 103(3) of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act 200 of 1993 (hereinafter the 1993 Constitution), for the proceedings to be postponed, pending an application to the Supreme Court regarding the constitutional status of s 2(1) of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Act 37 of 1967. The application was granted; proceedings in the Magistrates' Court were suspended and subsequently referred to the Witwatersrand Local Division of the Supreme Court. In appearing before Schabort J, the Case applicants entered a motion to have the matter referred to the Constitutional Court. The motion was granted and the matter duly referred. Proceedings against Curtis followed a parallel route to the Constitutional Court and the two cases were heard together by the Constitutional Court in September 1995.
84 Per Didcott J par [90] - par [95]; Chaskalson P, Mahomed DP, Ackermann J, Kriegler J, O'Regan J and Ngoepe AJ concurring.
85 Madala J par [105] preferred the term "sexually explicit erotica" instead.
86 Par [91].
87 Par [91].
88 "Photographic matter" was defined in the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Act 37 of 1967 as "including any photograph, photogravure and cinematograph film, and any pictorial representation intended for exhibition through the medium of a mechanical device".
89 Par [91].
90 S 2(1) of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Act 37 of 1967 read: "Any person who has in his possession any indecent or obscene photographic matter shall be guilty of an offence and liable on conviction to a fine not exceeding one thousand rand or imprisonment for a period not exceeding one year or to both such fine and such imprisonment". S 1 of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Act 37 of 1967 defined indecent or obscene photographic matter as follows: "Indecent or obscene matter includes photographic matter or any part thereof depicting, displaying, exhibiting, manifesting, portraying or representing sexual intercourse, licentiousness, lust, homosexuality, lesbianism, masturbation, sexual assault, rape, sodomy, masochism, sadism, sexual bestiality or anything of a like nature."
91 The applicants challenged s 2(1) of the Indecent or Obscene Photographic Matter Act 37 of 1967 on the basis of no fewer than five rights entrenched in the 1993 Constitution, namely s 8 (equality); s 13 (privacy); s 14(1) (freedom of conscience); s 15 (freedom of speech, expression and artistic creativity); s 24 (administrative justice); and s 33(1) (constitutionally permissible limitations of entrenched rights).
92 Par [92].
93 Par [93].
94 Par [93].
95 Par [93].
96 Par [17] - par [47].
97 Par [22].
98 Par [25].
99 Par [26].
100 Par [30] - par [34].
101 Par [35].
102 To be fair, even liberal feminist theory, which broadly supports arguments for the constitutional protection of adult gender-specific sexually explicit material, struggles to make political sense of this reality: see, for example, Pateman Feminist Critiques 118 and Morris Violence Against Women 352. See also Van Marle and Bonthuys Feminist Theories 31-32.
103 See Bronstein The Rape Complainant 202-227.
104 The radical feminist attack on the private/public distinction is not an attack on privacy as an ideal, nor does it advocate political involvement in personal and family life. Radical feminists simply seem to claim that the relations of family are political and should not be. See, in general, Van Marle and Bonthuys Feminist Theories 34-35.
105 Par [112].
106 See Clark Liberalism and Pornography 50.
107 Par [93].
108 See, in particular, par 6 and accompanying footnotes.
109 Par [93].
110 Per Didcott J par [93].
111 Per Madala J par [105].
112 Radical feminism distinguishes between erotica and pornography on the basis that the former bears three key characteristics which are distinctly absent from the latter. Erotic material, though sexually explicit: (a) does not subjugate women in its production or message; (b) does not involve coercion in its production, message or use; and (c) is devoid of any imminent or actual violence, including threats of violence. But since the majority of the Constitutional Court refused to even consider the (radical feminist) argument, presented by several amici curiae, that some link (or correlation) exists between acts of sexual violence against women and violent sexually explicit images, it cannot simply be taken for granted that the Constitutional Court subscribes to, and thereby embraces, this particular conception of erotica. Nor can it be assumed that the Constitutional Court is even aware of the distinction that (radical) feminists typically draw between so-called "erotic" as opposed to "pornographic" material.
113 Par [17].
114 Par [35].
115 Par [93].
116 See, in particular, Kois v Wisconsin 408 US 229 (1972) at 230, quoting Roth v United States 354 US 476 (1957) 489. See also par 3.4.1 n 54.
117 For a useful discussion of the philosophical underpinnings and justifications of freedom of expression, see, in general, Van der Westhuizen Freedom of Expression 267-270 and Currie and De Waal Expression 359-362.
118 In South African National Defence Force Union v Minister of Defence 1999 4 SA 469 (CC) par [7] and Kauesa v Minister of Home Affairs 1995 11 BCLR 1540 (NmS) (1554 C-D) and Banana v Attorney-General 1999 1 BCLR 27 (ZS) (31F). See also n 75.
119 See, in particular, the observations of O'Regan J in South African National Defence Force Union v Minister of Defence 1999 4 SA 469 (CC) par [8].
120 Case; Curtis v Minister of Safety and Security (n 83) per Didcott J par [94].

Creative Commons License Todo el contenido de esta revista, excepto dónde está identificado, está bajo una Licencia Creative Commons